[go: up one dir, main page]

Academia.eduAcademia.edu
Keynote Address Cultural cisgenderism: Consequences of the imperceptible Natacha Kennedy At the 2012 POWS Annual Conference, Natacha Kennedy delivered a powerful and challenging keynote on cultural cisgenderism. Her talk is reproduced here. Introduction: An inadequate metaphor THE FILM COMEDY I Was A Male War Bride (Hawks, 1949) depicted a newly married Frenchman played by Cary Grant attempting to accompany his American wife to the US at the end of World War Two. However, the US congress had only foreseen that American soldiers would be men and would be likely to marry European women. When an American servicewoman falls in love with a French soldier her efforts to ensure he can accompany her to America result in a huge, and in this instance, quite comic struggle with both bureaucracy and cultural expectations. As an illustration of the nature of cultural cisgenderism, it illustrates a similar kind of problem but in terms of extent is not nearly an adequate metaphor, yet it does represent an illustration of the difficulties faced by transgender people in a culture simply not constituted to account for our existence. The consequences of the War Brides Act 1945 are not, however, even remotely comparable with the very serious, and sometimes deadly, consequences of cultural cisgenderism. Nonetheless, as a metaphor it is probably the closest available, a point that in itself suggests that cisgenderism is a concept that will not be easy for many to understand. Situating cultural cisgenderism This paper intends to draw on and develop the research by Ansara and Hegarty (2012), which demonstrated how a group of psychology researchers have developed a culture of cisgenderism in what they identify as an ‘invisible college’. They characterised this type of cisgenderism as: ‘…a prejudicial ideology, rather than an individual attitude, that is systemic, multilevel and reflected in authoritative cultural discourses. […] Cisgenderism problematises the categorical distinction itself between classes of people as either ‘trans‐gender’ or ‘cisgender’ (or as ‘gender variant’ or unmarked) […] We consider cisgenderism to be a form of ‘othering’ that takes people categorised as ‘transgender’ as ‘the effect to be explained.’ (p.5) The distinction this paper intends to draw is between the type of cisgenderism Ansara and Hegarty describe, which appears to function within a particular esoteric domain, and cisgenderism within society as a whole. To do this I will need to refer to two sociological concepts, that of institutionalisation and that of discursive saturation (Dowling, 2009). In essence institutionalisation refers to the extent to which a practice is regular and widespread; a highly institutionalised practice is one that occurs in a similar way each time, whereas a weakly institutionalised practice occurs differently each time or is less regular in the way it is manifested. It is this that serves to distinguish cisgenderism from transphobia, since transphobia represents an individual attitude rather than a cultural process or ideology and as such can be characterised as weakly institutionalised. This will be explored in a little more detail below. Discursive saturation basically refers to the extent to which the principles of an activity may be expressed in language. A highly discursively saturated practice is dependent primarily, if not almost exclusively, on language for its functioning; an example of this would be mathematics. A weakly discursively saturated practice requires little or no language for it to function, for example, street football. It is this distinction that is crucial to the way cultural cisgenderism functions. As is shown in the relational space in Figure 1 below, the main differences between professional cisgenderism and cultural cisgenderism are the relative levels of discursive saturation. Psychology of Women Section Review – Vol. 15 No. 2 – Autumn 2013 3 © The British Psychological Society ISSN 1466–3724 Professional cisgenderism, in Ansara and Hegarty’s analysis, is relatively highly discursively saturated; the discourse of the invisible college was revealed, by detailed textual analysis, to represent an ‘authoritative cultural discourse’. So how is that different from the culture of cisgenderism outside the practice of psychology? In this case cultural cisgenderism represents a practice which has a similar level of institutionalisation but which has a relatively low level of discursive saturation. This is a culture or ideology (Geertz, 1973) which is predominantly tacitly held and communicated. It represents a systemic erasure and problematising of trans people, an essentialising of gender as binary, biologically determined, fixed at birth, immutable, natural and externally imposed on the individual. Of course, something characterised as a tacit ideology or culture is difficult to describe or analyse, but occasionally examples can be found where circumstances result in people having to explain their actions and as such put them into words. There follows one such example. In Denmark in 2010, the Danish Red Cross was running, as it still does at the time of writing, temporary accommodation for asylum‐seekers in Denmark for the Danish government at the Sandholm refugee camp, near Copenhagen. They received a new asylum seeker from Latin America who was a transgender woman. However, despite presenting as female and declaring a female identity they accommodated her in a single room in a mens’ dormitory. As a result she was repeatedly raped and eventually fled the camp after being gang‐raped. When later questioned about this the head of the Danish Red Cross asylum services told reporters the following; ‘Basically a transgender woman is likely to be placed in a male dormitory but in a single room. But we would not place her in a women’s dormitory because that is definitely for women, where we cannot permit ourselves to place a man.’ Modkraft, Denmark. August 2012. My own translation. Here there is no evidence that the head of asylum services intended deliberately to harm the victim by placing her in a dangerous situation where she would be raped. However, it does represent an example of cultural cisgenderism. It represents a confusion about gender resulting from the erasure of trans people in European culture. The Danish Red Cross, because it is an organisation existing in Western Europe, is affected by this cisgenderist culture. The above quotation reveals many of the features of cultural cisgenderism described above: • • • • • the systemic erasure and problematising of trans people; the essentialising of gender; the gender binary; the immutability of gender; the external imposition of gender. The problem for the victim is that, in this Case, the result would almost certainly have been the same if the head of asylum services at the Danish Red Cross had been transphobic. It is likely that in many cases, transphobia and cisgenderism have the same results. In particular it would appear that one of the most central elements of cultural cisgenderism is the way it places the responsibility for determining gender on the observer rather than the individual. In other words, in the culture of cisgenderism, gender is something we do to other people, not something people do for themselves. This external imposition of gender can be characterised as a lifelong process, one which, in most cases, begins at birth with gender assignation, and continues throughout life with gender attributions. This external imposition of gender can now be regarded as extended to transgender people with a bureaucratisation of gender transition, as transgender and transsexual people are referred to a psychologist or psychiatrist to have their new gender externally confirmed. It is worth comparing this with the culture in which two‐spirits were accommodated in native American culture (Williams 1992) where children who may identify as a gender other than the one assigned at birth had access to a symbolic ritual in which they were in effect, able to decide their own gender. Transphobia vs. Cisgenderism As I mentioned above it is necessary to distinguish cisgenderism from transphobia. The relational space situates transphobia in relation to cisgenderism. 2 Psychology of Women Section Review – Vol. 15 No. 2 – Autumn 2013 Natacha Kennedy Discursive Saturation High Discursive Saturation (DS+) Low Discursive Saturation (DS‐) Institutionalisation Strong Institutionalisation (I+) Weak Institutionalisation (I‐) Professional Organised Cisgenderism Transphobia Cultural Reactive Cisgenderism Transphobia Figure 1: Anti‐trans processes. Since it represents an individual attitude rather than a culture, it cannot be regarded as strongly institutionalised, although some transphobes have become organised and share a highly institutionalised internal culture of hatred, fear and hostility, these groups are relatively small in number. By way of example, within some religious groups and Trans Exclusionary Radical Feminists (TERFs) transphobic cultures exist which represent internally highly institutionalised transphobic ideologies. In these cases there exists a discourse of transphobia, which, in some cases, is required for the maintenance of their internal cohesion and in order to attempt to provide a rationalisation (Stone, 1991; Kaveney, 1979) for what appears to be little more than an emotional and irrational fear and hatred of trans people. This contrasts with what may be regarded as reactive transphobia, which exhibits low discursive saturation, which represents individuals whose fear, and consequently hatred, of trans people is openly based on the emotional and the irrational without drawing on the veneer of rationalisations. It is likely that this is a result of the exclusionary nature of cisgenderism and may often be attributed to portrayals of trans people in the media. However, in both these cases transphobia represents an individual attitude that stems from a fear and hatred of trans people. It should be made clear that this is not cisgenderism, indeed TERF transphobia largely represents a culture which mythologises a disguised essentialisation of gender, but only as far as trans people are concerned, presenting members of this group with rationalisations for what, in principle can only be described as shared emotional responses. As such a self‐perpetuating culture of hatred based on self‐deception is maintained. So cisgenderism is different from transphobia, in that transphobia represents an individual irrational hatred and fear (which in some circumstances may develop into its own micro culture as a means of justifying itself) whereas cisgenderism represents a much wider cultural process which in most cases is tacitly communicated. It is important to make this distinction. Interaction of professional and cultural cisgenderism By way of an illustration of how cisgenderism can function on a variety of levels, I would now like to present an analysis of one instance in which cultural cisgenderism results in unwarranted data and problematic assumptions, and to suggest that most research in psychology or neurology relating to trans people, cannot be reliable unless it takes account of cultural cisgenderism. Kraemer et al. (2005) and Landen and Rasmussen (1997) have suggested that there is a comorbidity between being transgender and being on the Autistic Spectrum (AS). Further studies have noted a higher instance of AS people who are trans (De Vries et al., 2010; Jones et al., 2011; Strang et al., 2012) but have gone no further than noting that a larger percentage of trans people are also AS. Although these articles clearly indicate a correlation, one might read into these studies an inference that there may be a causal link. There are two (related) problems with these studies and the first of these is that they fail to account for the effects of cultural cisgenderism. As a highly institutionalised culture, cisgenderism’s effects are relatively constant and uniform in most areas of society. However, as a culture that exhibits low discursive saturation cisgenderism is also tacitly communicated. This means that in most cases people come to internalise it without realising they are doing so. It is a set of beliefs which are usually picked up by children as a result of their finely tuned and sensitive social radar. The work of economist H.A. Simon (1976) is relevant here; he argued that, contrary to orthodox characterisations of human behaviour most people are not in the position to make objectively rational decisions about their lives and usually people Psychology of Women Section Review – Vol. 15 No. 2 – Autumn 2013 5 Cultural Cisgenderism: Consequences of the Imperceptible make decisions on the basis of inadequate and incomplete information. Trans children, like other children, understand that it is usually likely to be socially unacceptable to adopt certain behaviour, preferences or appearance, particularly those that are outside the social norms of their gendered community of practice (Paechter, 2007). The restricted nature of social groupings in primary and most secondary schools, and the lack of alternative social groupings available to those excluded from the school or class group, means that social exclusion represents a very real threat to them if they fail to conform to group norms. As such the decision by the majority of trans children to conceal their gender non‐conformity represents a rational one given the information available to them at the time. The tendency of trans children to conceal or suppress their gender identities (Kennedy, 2012) appears to arise, to a significant extent, from their perception of this tacitly expressed culture. However, there is one group of children for whom this tacit culture is either undetectable or unimportant: AS children. In most cases AS children would probably be unable to detect this tacit ideology; a process that results in most trans children concealing or suppressing their gender identities. Yet it is also probable that even if they did realise that it was socially unacceptable, most would be unlikely to be able to conceal it or to perceive the need to conceal. This presents us with an apparent paradox in which cultural cisgenderism is either not perceived or not perceived as important by AS children who are trans, whereas it affects non‐AS children who are trans to a far more significant extent. This results in those trans children who are AS becoming apparent much more readily than non‐ AS children because of the differential effects of cultural processes and social relations, in this case caused by cisgenderism. In effect cultural cisgenderism, because of its low discursive saturation, does not affect most AS children in the same way as it affects non‐AS children. The second problem would appear to be that the effects of professional cisgenderism have functioned in the instances cited above, to exclude from consideration by those carrying out the research the possibility that this cultural process might have an effect on their data, with the result that a comorbidity between being trans and being AS is argued or inferred. In effect cisgenderism has preempted the researchers from asking the most elementary question most researchers need to ask when a particular effect is observed; ‘What is this an instance of?’ (Dowling, 2009). By situating trans people as inherently problematic, and through its function of essentialising gender as immutable, fixed at birth and binary, cisgenderism appears to preclude researchers from perceiving the need even to ask this question or consider that there might be other causal links. So we can see how cisgenderism operates on two levels; within the group of people who are subjects of study, and by excluding important variables from consideration by part of the academic community studying them. The apparent attribution of a comorbidity between gender non‐conformity and autism/Asperger’s can be thus be attributed to a function of cisgenderism on two levels; professional cisgenderism and cultural cisgenderism. Of course, it is also likely that this also represents the effect of the restricted gaze of mainstream or quantitative psychological research and neurological research failing to account for social and cultural influences either on their research participants or on their own epistemological assumptions as researchers. Of course, there are other instances of the effects of cisgenderism resulting in researchers obtaining results that are probably unwarranted. Once again cisgenderism’s function has precluded asking the question ‘What is this effect an instance of?’ with the possibility at least acknowledged that there may be additional causal influences on the data. This is significant in the case of the substantial volume of research suggesting that the majority of trans or gender‐non‐conforming children do not grow up to be trans adults (e.g. Drescher & Byne, 2012; Drummond et al., 2008; Zucker, 1985). Repeated studies have asserted that anything between 70 per cent and 98 per cent of trans children do not become trans adults. However, this is difficult to argue when the effects of cultural cisgenderism are considered. Kennedy (2012) argues that the overwhelming majority of trans children conceal or suppress their gender nonconforming natures. Furthermore Sedgewick’s (1990) essay ‘Epistemology of the Closet’ demonstrated how difficult it is to come out as lesbian, gay or bisexual, yet applying the same epistemology of 4 Psychology of Women Section Review – Vol. 15 No. 2 – Autumn 2013 Natacha Kennedy the closet to trans children the effects of cisgenderism probably represent a much more significant hurdle for trans children than heteronormativity. For the majority of trans children not only is the fear of social exclusion evident, but cisgenderism also results in a lack of vocabulary being available for them to understand and communicate their experiences. This means that those children who do become apparent and available to researchers, are very unlikely to be representative of trans children as a group. It can be speculated that they may be subject to selection by at least three filters; becoming apparent to their parents, their parents not being happy to give their child the unconditional love they need to seek ‘treatment’ and subsequently being sufficiently determined to have a cisgender or heterosexual child to wish to subject them to psychologically coercive pressure to conform to the gender originally assigned to them at birth. Of course, cultural cisgenderism should be regarded as part of society’s perception of gender as largely essential. Messner’s (2000) observations of the way socially constructed gender differences in young children were attributed as essential by adults suggests that the majority perception of gender as essential persists quite strongly, indeed even trans people who campaign for trans human rights appear to consider essentialism as one of the core reasons for the existence of trans people: ‘There are probably many reasons for the increase in prevalence, including the increased dumping of environmental pollutants known as endocrine disruptors…’1 Dana Beyer, Executive Director of Gender Rights Maryland, 7 July 2013. The effects of cisgenderism, and in particular one of its constituent elements, essentialism, represent one of the many further hurdles for trans children and young trans people to overcome in addition to the problems that Sedgewick argues LGB people are likely to face in coming out. Of course, the above quotation suggests that trans people are also affected by cisgenderism, even as adults, and so, as children, it is likely to be much more difficult to become intelligible to oneself given the veiled nature of this process. However, it is also important to consider the effects of the cultural feedback loop created by the influence of professional cisgenderism on cultural cisgenderism. The perception given by this research, that, in most cases gender non‐conforming behaviour in children is considered a ‘phase’ suggests that the misconceptions propagated by some psychologists and neurologists are likely to form part of the wider cisgenderist culture and as such could be argued to represent a threat to the well‐being of most trans children through its contribution to the maintenance of cultural cisgenderist ideology in wider society. It is also particularly important to reiterate that cisgenderism is a culture/ideology that affects everyone. It affects the perceptions of trans people by others, and it disproportionately appears to affect trans children and young trans people. However, Butler’s characterisation of femininity as ‘the forcible citation of a norm.’ (Butler 1990) represents an indication that cisgenderism also affects those who do not identify as transgender, but which also acts to introduce a systemic element of coercion into the way women have to behave. Cisgenderism takes this further by arguing that this element of ‘forcibility’ is present for all genders not merely for feminine ones. Furthermore cisgenderism’s binary gendered coercive functioning results in those whose gender is different from that assigned at birth becoming delegitimised, unintelligible to others and to themselves and often systematically prevented from expressing their genders in any way at all. It is important to recognise that cultural cisgenderism is something that affects everyone both in terms of coercive restrictions on their own behaviour and appearance, and coercive misgendering and delegitimisation of those whose genders are not conventionally consistent with those attributed at birth. It is imperative, therefore, that professional communities, whether teachers, psychologists, doctors or others, acknowledge professional cisgenderism within their communities of practice and start to challenge its negative influence. The culture of cisgenderism within the wider community represents a more profound issue, and one, which cannot be so easily addressed. However, identifying cultural cisgenderism as a weakly discursively saturated culture/ideology may represent a means by which to resolve this issue. Weak discursive saturation represents one of its most significant characteristics so Psychology of Women Section Review – Vol. 15 No. 2 – Autumn 2013 7 Cultural Cisgenderism: Consequences of the Imperceptible the obvious question to raise would be whether or not it can exist as a relatively strongly discursively saturated practice. In other words if cisgenderism becomes an issue that is talked about more widely, will that in itself result in it becoming less of a problem? In any case the concept of cisgenderism and how it affects both transgender people and cisgender people needs to be more widely discussed, and instances of cisgenderism more clearly identified, in particular where they result in specific problems or disadvantages for individual trans people or groups of trans people. In a school context for example it is not sufficient for teachers to act to prevent transphobic bullying; one of the issues that is starting to be considered more. Schools need to consider how cisgenderism affects their treatment of trans children. Recent examples of cisgenderism in schools in the UK have included the following: • Lining up children in separate girl‐boy lines. • Refusing to allow trans girls to use the toilets of their choice or forcing them to use a toilet adapted for people with disabilities. • Teachers refusing to address transgender children by the name of their acquired gender, even when it is their legal name. • Headteachers refusing to discuss, with the legal representatives of the parents, allowing transgender children the right to express their gender in school. • Trans children who are bullied not being supported adequately by the school. • Trans children who come out as trans being regarded as the problem. • Schools refusing to recognise trans children’s human rights under the UN Convention of the Rights of the Child. • Parents of other children abusing trans children and the issue not being taken up by the school. Separate school uniforms for girls and boys preventing trans children from dressing in their real gender. • Schools trying to remove from the school roll trans children who no longer come to school because of bullying. • Schools treating trans children significantly differently from other children of their gender. • Schools attempting to force trans children to present and behave in the manner of a different gender. • • • Schools not adhering to the spirit and/or the letter of the Equality Act 2010. Schools not having equality and diversity policies that include gender reassignment. Schools providing staff training on lesbian, gay and bisexual issues but not trans issues.2 All of the above examples of trans children being treated less favourably represent examples of discrimination against trans children that have occurred in primary or secondary schools in the UK. Of course, it is possible that some of this represents direct transphobia on the part of senior staff in schools. However, it would appear that trans children occupy one of two default positions in relation to school. Firstly, the circumstances of the majority of trans children are that they are non‐apparent, and no‐one in the school is aware that they are trans. Because they are unable to be themselves and feel a strong sense of guilt and possibly self‐hatred because they are trans this is unlikely to be a good situation to be in from an educational perspective and is likely to result in their underperformance in school. Secondly, the circumstances of those who are openly trans is that they are likely to be unable to remain in school because of a combination of cisgenderism and transphobia. Either way the UK education system would seem to be failing trans children on a huge scale. This failure is compounded by a lack of recognition that this failure is occurring, and that action needs to be taken to remedy it. Trans children, as with all children, are supposedly protected by the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child (United Nations 1989), to which the UK is a signatory, yet their human rights are routinely denied, in particular Principles, 1, 2, 9 and 10. As an indirect result of these breaches, principle 7 (the right to an education) would also appear to be regularly breached. If this were occurring to any other groups there would be a huge outcry. Conclusion The weakly discursively saturated nature of cultural cisgenderism results in it being a culture or ideology that is difficult to recognise. This in turn renders it hard to understand its effects. However, it would seem that cisgenderism affects young trans people and trans children to a greater extent than most others in that it prevents the majority of 6 Psychology of Women Section Review – Vol. 15 No. 2 – Autumn 2013 Natacha Kennedy them from becoming intelligible to themselves and to those around them. The strongly institutionalised nature of cisgenderism combines with this to make it difficult for most people to understand that things they have considered to be taken from granted and to be naturally occurring are in fact socially constructed and harmful or exclusionary for trans people, even though there is no direct or overt intention to be transphobic or to harm trans people. Just as Cary Grant had to struggle against a system not designed for his individual circumstances, but which clearly was not intended to discriminate against heterosexual couples and prevent them from getting married, so cisgenderism represents a system against which trans people, especially trans children, have to struggle. The difference is that the sexist nature of the War Brides Act is easily exposed and relatively harmless. This is not the case for cisgenderism. It’s influence is very widespread, difficult to identify and its consequences can, and very often do, blight the entire lives of trans people, or worse. 1 http://www.huffingtonpost.com/dana‐beyer/gender‐ transition‐in‐children_b_3530335.html 2 Unfortunately it is not possible to reveal the exact details of these occurrences without breaching the individual children’s rights to privacy, however, they have all occurred between 2008 and 2013 in schools in the UK. Correspondence Natacha Kennedy Goldsmiths, University of London. Ansara, G. & Hegarty, P. (2011). Cisgenderism in psychology: Pathologising and misgendering children from 1999 to 2008. Psychology & Sexuality, 3(2), 137–160. Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble. New York: Routledge. Drescher, J. & Byne, W. (2012). Gender Dysphoric/ Gender Variant (GD/GV) children and adolescents: Summarising what we know and what we have yet to learn. Journal of Homosexuality, 59(3), 501–510. De Vries, A., Noens, I., Cohen‐Kettenis, P., Van Berckelaer‐Onnes, I. & Dorelijers, T. (2010). Autism spectrum disorders in gender dysphoric children and adolescents. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 40(8), 930–936. Drummond, K., Bradley, S., Peterson‐Badali, M. & Zucker, K. (2008). A follow‐up study of girls with gender identity disorder. Developmental Psychology, 44, 34–45. Dowling, P. (2009). Sociology as method: Beyond the forensics of culture, text and knowledge. Rotterdam: Sense. Geertz, C. (1973). Ideology as a cultural system. In C. Geertz, Interpretation of cultures: Selected essays. New York: Basic Books. Hawks, H. (1949). I Was A Male War Bride. Jones, R., Wheelwright, S., Farrell, K., Martin, E., Green, R., Di Ceglie, D. & Baron‐Cohen, S. (2011). Brief report: Female‐to‐Male transsexual people and autistic traits. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 42, 301–306. Kaveney, R. (1979). Janice Raymond: The transsexual empire. Originally published in Gay News. http://rozk.livejournal.com/173751.html Kennedy, N (2012). Transgender children: More than a theoretical challenge. Updated version 2012 – originally published in Graduate Journal of Social Science, 7(2). http://transkids.synthasite.com/resources/ NatachaKennedy%20(2010)%20‐%20 updated%20version.pdf Messner, M. (2000). Barbie girls versus sea monsters: Children constructing gender. Gender and Society, 14(6). Paechter, C. (2007). Being boys, being girls: Learning masculinities and femininities. Maidenhead: Open University Press. Sedgewick, E. (1990). Epistemology of the closet. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Simon, H. (1976). From substantive to procedural rationality. In S. Latsis (Ed.), Method and appraisal in economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stone, S. (1991). The empire strikes back: A posttranssexual manifesto. In K. Straub & J. Epstein (Eds.) (1992), Body guards: The cultural politics of gender ambiguity. New York: Routledge. Strang, J. et al. (2012). Increased rates of gender identity issues among children and adolescents with autism spectrum disorders. International Society for Autism Research. https://imfar.confex.com/imfar/2012/ webprogram/Paper10934.html United Nations (1989). United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child. http://www.ohchr.org/EN/ ProfessionalInterest/Pages/CRC.aspx Williams, W. (1992). The spirit and the flesh: Sexual diversity in American Indian culture. New York: Beacon. Zucker, K. (1985). Cross‐gender identified children. In B.W. Steiner (Ed.), Gender dysphoria: Development, research, management (pp.75–174). New York: Plenum Press. Psychology of Women Section Review – Vol. 15 No. 2 – Autumn 2013 Natacha Kennedy